In the Nick Rowe blog post I linked to in the previous blog post, he outlines the views of the economic world this way:
“There are 4 possible positions to take on the
debt. One of them doesn't make sense; the other 3 do. Which of those 3 is right
is an empirical question.
Here are the 4 positions. I gave each one a name. I
made up the quotes.
1. Abba Lerner. 'The national debt is not a first-order burden on future
generations. We owe it to ourselves. The sum of the IOU's must equal the sum of
the UOMe's. You can't make real goods and services travel back in time, out of
the mouths of our grandkids and into our mouths. The possible second-order
exceptions are: if we owe it to foreigners; the disincentive effects of
distortionary future taxes; the lower marginal product of future labour if the
future capital stock is smaller.'
2. James Buchanan/uneducated person on the
street. 'The national debt is a burden
on future generations of taxpayers. Foreigners are basically irrelevant. Any
second order effects of distortionary taxes and lower capital stock are over
and above that first order effects of the taxes themselves.'
3. Robert Barro/Ricardian Equivalence. 'The national debt is not a burden on future
taxpayers (except for the deadweight costs of distortionary taxation) but only
because ordinary people take steps to fully offset the burden on future
generations by increasing private saving to offset government dissaving and
increasing bequests to their heirs to offset the debt burden.'
4. Samuelson 1958. 'If the rate of interest on government bonds is forever less than
the growth rate of the economy, the government can run a sustainable Ponzi
finance of deficits, where it rolls over the debt plus interest forever and
never needs to increase taxes, so there is no burden on future generations.'
I personally was taught 1 as an undergraduate. And
I believed in 1 until about 1980, when I spent some time reading Buchanan and
Barro arguing with each other. And I worked 4 into my own beliefs soon after.
And now, I believe 1 is false. The truth is some
sort of mixture of 2,3, and 4. What precise mixture of 2,3,4 is true is an
empirical question. My prior is one third-one third-one third.”
So, from the quote above, the answer from the world of
economics to the question “does the debt burden future generations” is “no”,
“yes”, “it would if all the valiant people didn’t sacrifice themselves to
prevent it”, and “we’ll be ok if we can keep up with the payments”.
Well that’s helpful,
isn’t it?
I agree with Rowe when he says that three of these make
sense and one doesn’t, but I don’t agree with him about which one doesn’t. I think the first and second
views are both largely correct even though they seem to be opposites---I’ll
explain below---and I think the fourth is self evidently true, although I don’t
think the use of the word “Ponzi” is appropriate here since the universe of
players is not finite.
But the third makes no sense at all to me. I’ll explain more in a later post, but just
as a first practical point I’ll observe that no one I know behaves like
that. No one bases their current
savings/consumption decisions on what taxes might be in twenty years. Not even people with doctorates in economics
who are brave enough to hazard a wild guess about future tax rates behave like
that, largely because they all know that no matter how good they are their
guess about things that far away is likely to be wrong. But to the average person who does not
study economics the future debt, while it may be a scary phantom in the woods that grabs their vote,
is a distant abstraction in daily life. It
doesn’t change the fact that they need a new dishwasher. So even if it worked theoretically (and I don't think it does) it
would not describe a real process that exists in the real world.
At the end of his post he adds this:
“But my brain just can't figure it
out, yet. Maybe some of you younger, keener, brighter, people could work on
this?”
I’m pretty sure I’m not any younger than Nick Rowe, and I
certainly can’t claim to be brighter, but maybe if I explain how I see this it
will spark something that will lead him, or someone, to some kind of progress
in this long debate.
So to start, let me say that I think the people in the four
views above are talking past each other, talking about different things using
different conceptual tools.
In view number 1 Abba Lerner is talking about physical
stuff, the real economy, houses and trucks
and grapes, not accounting or finance.
Lerner does get into finance---functional finance, which is really fun
(no, really!), and which I’ll describe in a day or two in very rudimentary form as a treat
for those who haven’t heard of it before---but the concept in Rowe’s quote is
about physical things, and makes the point I started with several blog posts
ago: we can’t eat the carrots from future gardens, so as long as we continue to
invest and educate our children and all the rest of the things that will impact
future productive capacity, we can’t grab their things and consume them now. They, in the future, will divide up
among themselves the same amount of stuff whether we have a federal debt at
that time or not. The idea that
“we owe it to ourselves” means that we shift the right to consume among
the people who are around in that future period, but the loss to some is a gain
to others, so on the whole, as a country, we have not lost anything.
In view number 2 Buchanan is talking about the inner life of people: he’s saying that the amount of material
satisfaction, or for econ people
utility, can change from one period to
another, or even within a period, even if the amount of stuff available for
consumption doesn’t. This is a
discussion of personal choice, and of a utility burden rather than a financial
burden. It’s entirely possible to
concede that the amount of stuff is unaffected by debt, but to argue that the
burden in terms of utility falls completely on the later group---and in some
places Buchanan does exactly that, in a very simple way. He points out that in the first time
period, when some people purchase government debt, they do so voluntarily so
they must be happier buying the bonds than they would have been if they had
bought consumption goods instead. In the first period, the bond buyers are better off, in terms of their satisfaction with what they buy. But in the second period the bonds must be
paid off by taxing the population, which is a direct loss to each of the
taxpayers. So the people in
the first period are more satisfied with life, while the people in the second
are less satisfied with life.
Views 3 and 4 both seem to me to be talking about finance,
that is, not about the amount of physical stuff available or about how
satisfied we are consuming them, but about how and when we pay for them.
As I said before, I think 3 is a puffy concoction created
solely to support a contention that the government has no impact on the real
world, a contention which is completely and obviously false. It does have the
virtue that it gets a bit beyond finance alone and talks about human reactions
to financial events, which is to say that it gets into actual economic
behavior, but the assertion it makes about how humans react seems wholly
unreal. Sorry, I don’t mean to be
harsh, but that’s how it looks to me.
But I’ll expand on that later, and readers can savage me at their
whim.
View 4 is just a basic statement of good investment: if your
returns are greater than the cost of borrowing, you come out ahead.
It’s late, and dinner is calling, so I’ll continue
tomorrow. But tomorrow I’ll look
first at a variation that isn’t really listed above: crowding out. That’s the assertion that government
borrowing displaces private investment, so in the end it has to reduce future
productive capacity, and future consumption. And I’ll start with the most boneheaded possible version, the
assertion that savings equals investment as an accounting identity, so
there's no way around it: when government deficits go up investment must go down.
Some very good economists have said things like this. And it’s completely, incredibly wrong.
No comments:
Post a Comment